Dictionary Definition
practical adj
1 concerned with actual use or practice; "he is a
very practical person"; "the idea had no practical application"; "a
practical knowledge of Japanese"; "woodworking is a practical art"
[ant: impractical]
2 guided by practical experience and observation
rather than theory; "a hardheaded appraisal of our position"; "a
hard-nosed labor leader"; "completely practical in his approach to
business"; "not ideology but pragmatic politics" [syn: hardheaded, hard-nosed,
pragmatic]
3 being actually such in almost every respect; "a
practical failure"; "the once elegant temple lay in virtual ruin"
[syn: virtual(a),
practical(a)]
4 having or put to a practical purpose or use;
"practical mathematics"; "practical applications of calculus"
User Contributed Dictionary
English
Pronunciation
- /ˈpræktɪkəl/, /"pr
Extensive Definition
Pragmatism is a philosophic
school generally considered to have originated in the late
nineteenth century with Charles
Peirce, who first stated the pragmatic
maxim. It came to fruition in the early twentieth-century
philosophies of William
James and John Dewey.
Most of the thinkers who describe themselves as pragmatists
consider practical consequences or real effects to be vital
components of both meaning and truth. Other important aspects of
pragmatism include anti-Cartesianism,
radical
empiricism, instrumentalism,
anti-realism,
verificationism,
conceptual
relativity, a denial of the fact-value
distinction, a high regard for science, and fallibilism.
Pragmatism began enjoying
renewed attention from the 1950s on, because of a new school of
philosophers who put forth a revised pragmatism that criticized the
logical
positivism that had dominated philosophy in the United States
and Britain since the 1930s, notably in the work of analytic
philosophers like W.
V. O. Quine and Wilfrid
Sellars. Their naturalized
epistemology was further developed and widely publicized by
Richard
Rorty, whose later work grew closer to continental
philosophy and is often considered relativistic. Contemporary
pragmatism is still divided between those thinkers who work
strictly within the analytic tradition, and a more relativistic
strand in the wake of Rorty and lastly neoclassical pragmatists
like Susan Haack
who stay closer to the work of Peirce, James and
Dewey.
Origins
As a philosophical movement,
pragmatism originated in the United
States in the late 1800s. The thought
and works of Charles
Sanders Peirce () and William
James (both members of The
Metaphysical Club) as well as John Dewey and
George
Herbert Mead figured most prominently in its overall direction.
The term pragmatism was first used in print by James, who credited
Peirce with coining the term during the early 1870s. Prompted by
James' use of the term and its attribution to him, Peirce began
writing and lecturing on pragmatism to make clear his own
interpretation. Peirce eventually coined the new name pragmaticism to mark what
he regarded as the original idea, for clarity's sake and possibly
(but not certainly) because he disagreed with James (cf. Menand
2001 on the former interpretation; below on the latter). He claimed
that the term was so ugly, nobody would be tempted to steal it
(Haack 1998).
James and Peirce were inspired
by several earlier thinkers, notably Alexander
Bain, who examined the crucial links among belief, conduct, and
disposition by
saying that a belief is a proposition on which a person is prepared
to act. Earlier thinkers that inspired the pragmatists include
Francis
Bacon who coined the phrase "knowledge is power", David Hume for
his naturalistic account of knowledge and action, Thomas Reid
for his direct
realism, Immanuel
Kant for his idealism and from whom Peirce derives the name
"pragmatism", Georg Hegel for his introduction of temporality into
philosophy (Pinkard in Misak 2007), and J.S. Mill for
his nominalism and empiricism.
Pragmatist epistemology
The epistemology of the early pragmatists was heavily influenced by Darwinian thinking. Pragmatists were not the first to see the relevance of evolution for theories of knowledge: the same rationale had for example convinced Schopenhauer that we should adopt biological idealism because what's useful to an organism to believe might differ wildly from what is actually true. Pragmatism differs from this idealist account because it challenges the assumption that knowledge and action are two separate spheres, and that there exists an absolute or transcendental truth above and beyond the sort of inquiry that organisms use to cope with life. Pragmatism, in short, provides what might be termed an ecological account of knowledge: inquiry is construed as a means by which organisms can get a grip on their environment. 'Real' and 'true' are labels that have a function in inquiry and cannot be understood outside of that context. It is not realist in a traditional robust sense of realism (what Hilary Putnam would later call metaphysical realism), but it is realist in that it acknowledges an external world which must be dealt with.A general tendency by
philosophers to push all views into either the idealist or realist
camp, as well as William James' occasional penchant for eloquence
at the expense of public understanding, resulted in the widespread
but false characterization of pragmatism as a form of subjectivism or idealism. Many of James'
best-turned phrases — "truth's cash value" (James 1907, p. 200) and
"the true is only the expedient in our way of thinking" (James
1907, p. 222) — were taken out of context and caricatured in
contemporary literature as representing the view that any idea that
has practical utility is true. William James writes:
In reality, James asserts, the
theory is a great deal more subtle. (See Dewey 1910 for a
'FAQ')
Pragmatists do disagree with
the view that beliefs must represent reality to be true - "Copying
is one [and only one] genuine mode of knowing" says James (James
1907, p. 91) - and argue that beliefs are dispositions which
qualify as true or false depending on how helpful they prove in
inquiry and in action. It is only in the struggle of intelligent
organisms with the surrounding environment that theories acquire
meaning, and only with a theory's success in this struggle that it
becomes true. However most pragmatists do not hold that anything
that is practical or useful, or that anything that helps to survive
merely in the short term, should be regarded as true. For example,
to believe that my cheating spouse is faithful may help me feel
better now, but it is certainly not useful from a more long-term
perspective because it doesn't accord with the facts (and is
therefore not true).
Concept of truth
Going back to James, pragmatists have often spoken of how truth is not ready-made, but that jointly we and reality "make" truth. This idea has two senses, one which is often attributed to William James and F.C.S. Schiller, and another that is more widely accepted by pragmatists: (1) that truth is mutable, and (2) truth is relative to a conceptual scheme.(1) Mutability of
truth
One major difference among the
pragmatists about the definition of 'truth' is the question of
whether beliefs can pass from being true to being untrue and back.
For James, beliefs are not true until they have been made true by
verification. James believed propositions become true over the long
term through proving their utility in a person's specific
situation. The opposite of this process is not falsification, but
rather a belief ceasing to be a "live option." F.C.S. Schiller, on
the other hand, very clearly asserted that beliefs could pass into
and out of truth situationally. Schiller held that truth was
relative to specific problems. If I want to know how to return home
safely, the true answer will be whatever is useful to solving that
problem. Later on, when faced with a different problem, what I came
to believe when faced with the earlier problem may now be false. As
my problems change and as the most useful way to solve a problem
shifts, so does the property of truth.
C.S. Peirce thought the idea
that beliefs could be true at one time but false at another (or
true for one person but false for another) was one of the "seeds of
death" by which James allowed his pragmatism to become "infected."
Peirce avoided this position because he took the pragmatic theory
to imply that theoretical claims should be tied to verification
practices (i.e. they should be subject to test), not that they
should be tied to our specific problems or life needs. Truth is
defined, for Peirce, as what would be the ultimate outcome (not any
outcome in real time) of inquiry by a (usually scientific)
community of investigators. John Dewey, while agreeing broadly with
this definition, also characterized truthfulness as a species of
the good: to state that something is true means stating that it is
trustworthy or reliable and will remain so in every conceivable
situation. Both Peirce and Dewey clearly connect the definitions of
truth and warranted assertability. Hilary Putnam also developed his
internal
realism around the idea that a belief is true if it is ideally
epistemically justified. About James' and Schiller's account,
Putnam says this:
Rorty has also weighed in
against James and Schiller:
(2) Conceptual
Relativity
Part of what James and
Schiller mean by the phrase 'making truth' is their idea that we
make things true by verifying them. This sense of 'making truth'
has not been adopted by many other pragmatists. However, there is
another sense to this phrase that nearly all pragmatists do adopt.
It is the idea that there can be no truths without a conceptual
scheme to express those truths. That is,
F.C.S. Schiller used the
analogy of a chair to make clear what he meant by the phrase that
truth is made: just as a carpenter makes a chair out of existing
materials and doesn't create it out of nothing, truth is a
transformation of our experience but that doesn't imply reality is
something we're free to construct or imagine as we
please.
Central pragmatist tenets
The primacy of practice
The pragmatist proceeds from the basic premise that the human capability of theorizing is integral to intelligent practice. Theory and practice are not separate spheres; rather, theories and distinctions are tools or maps for finding our way in the world. As John Dewey put it, there is no question of theory versus practice but rather of intelligent practice versus uninformed, stupid practice and noted in a conversation with William Pepperell Montague that "[h]is effort had not been to practicalize intelligence but to intellectualize practice". (Quoted in Eldridge 1998, p. 5) Theory is an abstraction from direct experience and ultimately must return to inform experience in turn. Thus an organism navigating his or her environment is the grounds for pragmatist inquiry.Anti-reification of concepts and theories
Dewey, in The Quest For Certainty, criticized what he called "the philosophical fallacy": philosophers often take categories (such as the mental and the physical) for granted because they don't realize that these are merely nominal concepts that were invented to help solve specific problems. This causes metaphysical and conceptual confusion. Various examples are the "ultimate Being" of Hegelian philosophers, the belief in a "realm of value", the idea that logic, because it is an abstraction from concrete thought, has nothing to do with the act of concrete thinking, and so on. David L. Hildebrand sums up the problem: "Perceptual inattention to the specific functions comprising inquiry led realists and idealists alike to formulate accounts of knowledge that project the products of extensive abstraction back onto experience." (Hildebrand 2003)Naturalism and anti-Cartesianism
From the outset, pragmatists wanted to reform philosophy and bring it more in line with the scientific method as they understood it. They argued that idealist and realist philosophy had a tendency to present human knowledge as something beyond what science could grasp. These philosophies then resorted either to a phenomenology inspired by Kant or to correspondence theories of knowledge and truth. Pragmatists criticized the former for its a priorism, and the latter because it takes correspondence as an unanalyzable fact. Pragmatism instead tries to explain, psychologically and biologically, how the relation between knower and known 'works' in the world.In "The
Fixation of Belief" (1877), C.S. Peirce denied that
introspection and intuition (staple philosophical tools at least
since Descartes) were valid methods for philosophical
investigation. He argued that intuition could lead to faulty
reasoning, e.g. when we reason intuitively about infinity.
Furthermore, introspection does not give privileged access to
knowledge about the mind - the self is a concept that is derived
from our interaction with the external world and not the other way
around. (De Waal 2005, pp. 7-10) By the time of his Harvard
Lectures in 1903, however, he had become convinced that pragmatism
and epistemology in general could not be derived from principles of
psychology: what we do think is too different from what we should
think. This is an important point of disagreement with most other
pragmatists, who advocate a more thorough naturalism and
psychologism.
Richard Rorty expanded on
these and other arguments in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature in
which he criticized attempts by many philosophers of science to
carve out a space for epistemology that is entirely unrelated to -
and sometimes thought of as superior to - the empirical sciences.
W.V. Quine, instrumental in bringing naturalized
epistemology back into favor with his essay Epistemology
Naturalized (Quine 1969), also criticized 'traditional'
epistemology and its "Cartesian dream" of absolute certainty. The
dream, he argued, was impossible in practice as well as misguided
in theory because it separates epistemology from scientific
inquiry.
The reconciliation of anti-skepticism and fallibilism
Hilary Putnam suggests that the reconciliation of antiskepticism and fallibilism is the central goal of American pragmatism. Although all human knowledge is partial, with no ability to take a 'God's-eye-view,' this does not necessitate a globalized skeptical attitude. Peirce insisted that contrary to Descartes' famous and influential methodology in the Meditations on First Philosophy, doubt cannot be feigned or created for the purpose of conducting philosophical inquiry. Doubt, like belief, requires justification. It arises from confrontation with some specific recalcitrant matter of fact (which Dewey called a 'situation'), which unsettles our belief in some specific proposition. Inquiry is then the rationally self-controlled process of attempting to return to a settled state of belief about the matter. Note that anti-skepticism is a reaction to modern academic skepticism in the wake of Descartes. The pragmatist insistence that all knowledge is tentative is actually quite congenial to the older skeptical tradition.Pragmatism in other fields of philosophy
While pragmatism started out simply as a criterion of meaning, it quickly expanded to become a full-fledged epistemology with wide-ranging implications for the entire philosophical field. Pragmatists who work in these fields share a common inspiration, but their work is diverse and there are no received views.Philosophy of science
In the philosophy of science, instrumentalism is the view that concepts and theories are merely useful instruments whose worth is measured not by whether the concepts and theories somehow mirror reality, but by how effective they are in explaining and predicting phenomena. Instrumentalism does not state that truth doesn't matter, but rather provides a specific answer to the question of what truth and falsity mean and how they function in science.One of C.I. Lewis'
main arguments in Mind and the World Order: Outline of a Theory of
Knowledge was that science does not merely provide a copy of
reality but must work with conceptual systems and that those are
chosen for pragmatic reasons, that is, because they aid inquiry.
Lewis' own development of multiple modal logics
is a case in point. Lewis is sometimes called a 'conceptual
pragmatist' because of this. (Lewis 1929)
Another development is the
cooperation of logical
positivism and pragmatism in the works of Charles
W. Morris and Rudolph
Carnap. The influence of pragmatism on these writers is mostly
limited to the incorporation of the pragmatic
maxim into their epistemology. Pragmatists with a broader
conception of the movement don't often refer to them.
W. V.
Quine's paper "Two
Dogmas of Empiricism," published 1951, is one of the most
celebrated papers of twentieth-century philosophy in the analytic
tradition. The paper is an attack on two central tenets of the
logical positivists' philosophy. One is the distinction between
analytic truths, statements which are true simply in value of the
meanings of their words ('all bachelors are unmarried'), and
synthetic truths, which are grounded in empirical fact. The other
is reductionism, the theory that each meaningful statement gets its
meaning from some logical construction of terms which refers
exclusively to immediate experience. Quine's argument brings to
mind Peirce's insistence that axioms aren't a priori truths but
synthetic statements.
Logic
Later in his life Schiller became famous for his attacks on logic in his textbook "Formal Logic." By then, Schiller's pragmatism had become the nearest of any of the classical pragmatists to an ordinary language philosophy. Schiller sought to undermine the very possibility of formal logic, by showing that words only had meaning when used in an actual context. The least famous of Schiller's main works was the constructive sequel to his destructive book "Formal Logic." In this sequel, "Logic for Use," Schiller attempted to construct a new logic to replace the formal logic he had just decimated in "Formal Logic." What he offers is something philosophers would recognize today as a logic covering the context of discovery and the hypothetico-deductive method.Whereas F.C.S. Schiller
actually dismissed the possibility of formal logic, most
pragmatists are critical rather of its pretension to ultimate
validity and see logic as one logical tool among others - or
perhaps, considering the multitude of formal logics, one set of
tools among others. This is the view of C.I. Lewis. C.S. Peirce
developed multiple methods for doing formal logic.
Stephen Toulmin's The Uses of
Argument inspired scholars in informal logic and rhetoric studies
(although it is actually an epistemological work).
Metaphysics
James and Dewey were empirical thinkers in the most straightforward fashion: experience is the ultimate test and experience is what needs to be explained. They were dissatisfied with ordinary empiricism because in the tradition dating from Hume, empiricists had a tendency to think of experience as nothing more than individual sensations. To the pragmatists, this went against the spirit of empiricism: we should try to explain all that is given in experience including connections and meaning, instead of explaining them away and positing sense data as the ultimate reality. Radical empiricism, or Immediate Empiricism in Dewey's words, wants to give a place to meaning and value instead of explaining them away as subjective additions to a world of whizzing atoms.William James gives an
interesting example of this philosophical shortcoming: F.C.S.
Schiller's first book, "Riddles of the Sphinx", was published
before he became aware of the growing pragmatist movement taking
place in America. In it, Schiller argues for a middle ground
between materialism and absolute metaphysics. The result of the
split between these two explanatory schemes that are comparable to
what William James called tough-minded empiricism and tender-minded
rationalism, Schiller contends, is that mechanicistic naturalism
cannot make sense of the "higher" aspects of our world (freewill,
consciousness, purpose, universals and some would add God), while
abstract metaphysics cannot make sense of the "lower" aspects of
our world (the imperfect, change, physicality). While Schiller is
vague about the exact sort of middle ground he is trying to
establish, he suggests metaphysics as a tool that can aid inquiry
and is only valuable insofar as it actually does help in
explanation.
In the second half of the
twentieth century, Stephen
Toulmin argued that the need to distinguish between reality and
appearance only arises within an explanatory scheme and therefore
that there is no point in asking what 'ultimate reality' consists
of. More recently, a similar idea has been suggested by the
postanalytical philosopher Daniel
Dennett, who argues that anyone who wants to understand the
world has to adopt the intentional stance and acknowledge both the
'syntactical' aspects of reality (i.e. whizzing atoms) and its
emergent or 'semantic' properties (i.e. meaning and
value).
Radical Empiricism gives
interesting answers to questions about the limits of science if
there are any, the nature of meaning and value and the workability
of reductionism.
These questions feature prominently in current debates about the
relationship between religion and science, where it is often
assumed - most pragmatists would disagree - that science degrades
everything that is meaningful into 'merely' physical
phenomena.
Philosophy of mind
Both John Dewey in Nature and Experience (1929) and half a century later Richard Rorty in his monumental Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979) argued that much of the debate about the relation of the mind to the body results from conceptual confusions. They argue instead that there is no need to posit the mind or mindstuff as an ontological category.Pragmatists disagree over
whether philosophers ought to adopt a quietist or a naturalist
stance toward the mind-body problem. The former (Rorty among them)
want to do away with the problem because they believe it's a
pseudo-problem, whereas the latter believe that it is a meaningful
empirical question.
Ethics
Pragmatism sees no fundamental difference between practical and theoretical reason, nor any ontological difference between facts and values. Both facts and values have cognitive content: knowledge is what we should believe; values are hypotheses about what is good in action. Pragmatist ethics is broadly humanist because it sees no ultimate test of morality beyond what matters for us as humans. Good values are those for which we have good reasons, viz. the Good Reasons approach. The pragmatist formulation pre-dates those of other philosophers who have stressed important similarities between values and facts such as Jerome Schneewind and John Searle.William James contribution to
ethics, as laid out in his essay The Will to Believe has often been
misunderstood as a plea for relativism or irrationality. On its own
terms it argues that ethics always involves a certain degree of
trust or faith and that we cannot always wait for adequate proof
when making moral decisions. Of the classical pragmatists, John
Dewey wrote most extensively about morality and democracy. (Edel
1993) In his classic article Three Independent Factors in Morals
(Dewey 1930), he tried to integrate three basic philosophical
perspectives on morality: the right, the virtuous and the good. He
held that while all three provide meaningful ways to think about
moral questions, the possibility of conflict among the three
elements cannot always be easily solved. (Anderson,
SEP)
Dewey also criticized the
dichotomy between means and ends which he saw as responsible for
the degradation of our everyday working lives and education, both
conceived as merely a means to an end. He stressed the need for
meaningful labor and a conception of education that viewed it not
as a preparation for life but as life itself. (Dewey 2004 [1910]
ch. 7; Dewey 1997 [1938], p. 47)
Dewey was opposed to other
ethical philosophies of his time, notably the emotivism of Alfred Ayer.
Dewey envisioned the possibility of ethics as an experimental
discipline, and thought values could best be characterized not as
feelings or imperatives, but as hypotheses about what actions will
lead to satisfactory results or what he termed consummatory
experience. A further implication of this view is that ethics is a
fallible undertaking, since human beings are frequently unable to
know what would satisfy them.
A recent pragmatist
contribution to meta-ethics is
Todd Lekan's "Making Morality" (Lekan 2003). Lekan argues that
morality is a fallible but rational practice and that it has
traditionally been misconceived as based on theory or principles.
Instead, he argues, theory and rules arise as tools to make
practice more intelligent.
Aesthetics
John Dewey's Art as Experience, based on the William James lectures he delivered at Harvard, was an attempt to show the integrity of art, culture and everyday experience. (Field, IEP) Art, for Dewey, is or should be a part of everyone's creative lives and not just the privilege of a select group of artists. He also emphasizes that the audience is more than a passive recipient. Dewey's treatment of art was a move away from the transcendental approach to aesthetics in the wake of Immanuel Kant who emphasized the unique character of art and the disinterested nature of aesthetic appreciation.A notable contemporary
pragmatist aesthetician is Joseph
Margolis. He defines a work of art as "a physically embodied,
culturally emergent entity", a human "utterance" that isn't an
ontological quirk but in line with other human activity and culture
in general. He emphasizes that works of art are complex and
difficult to fathom, and that no determinate interpretation can be
given.
Philosophy of religion
Both Dewey and James have investigated the role that religion can still play in contemporary society, the former in A Common Faith and the latter in The Varieties of Religious Experience.It should be noted, from a
general point of view, that for William James, something is true
only insofar as it works. Thus, the statement, for example, that
prayer is heard may work on a psychological level but (a) will not
actually help to bring about the things you pray for (b) may be
better explained by referring to its soothing effect than by
claiming prayers are actually heard. As such, pragmatism isn't
antithetical to religion but it isn't an apologetic for faith
either.
Joseph
Margolis, in Historied Thought, Constructed World (California,
1995), makes a distinction between "existence" and "reality". He
suggests using the term "exists" only for those things which
adequately exhibit Pierce's Secondness: things which offer brute
physical resistance to our movements. In this way, such things
which affect us, like numbers, may be said to be "real", though
they do not "exist". Margolis suggests that God, in such a
linguistic usage, might very well be "real", causing believers to
act in such and such a way, but might not "exist".
Analytical, neoclassical and neopragmatism
Neopragmatism is a broad contemporary category used for various thinkers, some of them radically opposed to one another. The name neopragmatist signifies that the thinkers in question incorporate important insights of, and yet significantly diverge from, the classical pragmatists. This divergence may occur either in their philosophical methodology (many of them are loyal to the analytic tradition) or in actual conceptual formation (C.I. Lewis was very critical of Dewey; Richard Rorty dislikes Peirce). Important analytical neopragmatists include the aforementioned Lewis, W.V.O. Quine, Donald Davidson, Hilary Putnam and the early Richard Rorty. Stanley Fish, the later Rorty and Jürgen Habermas are closer to continental thought.Neoclassical pragmatism
denotes those thinkers who consider themselves inheritors of the
project of the classical pragmatists. Sidney Hook
and Susan
Haack (known for the theory of foundherentism) are
well-known examples.
Not all pragmatists are easily
characterized. It is probable, considering the advent of postanalytic
philosophy and the diversification of Anglo-American
philosophy, that more philosophers will be influenced by pragmatist
thought without necessarily publicly committing themselves to that
philosophical school. Daniel
Dennett, a student of Quine's, falls into this category, as
does Stephen
Toulmin, who arrived at his philosophical position via Wittgenstein,
whom he calls "a pragmatist of a sophisticated kind" (foreword for
Dewey 1929 in the 1988 edition, p. xiii). Another example is
Mark
Johnson whose embodied
philosophy (Lakoff and Johnson 1999) shares its psychologism,
direct realism and anti-cartesianism with pragmatism. Conceptual
pragmatism is a theory of knowledge originating with the work of
the philosopher and logician Clarence
Irving Lewis. The epistemology of conceptual pragmatism was
first formulated in the 1929 book Mind and the World Order: Outline
of a Theory of Knowledge.
'French Pragmatism' is
attended with theorists like Bruno
Latour, Michel
Crozier and Luc
Boltanski and Laurent
Thévenot. It is often seen as opposed to structural problems
connected to the French Critical
Theory of Pierre
Bourdieu.
Contemporary echoes and ties
In the twentieth century, the movements of logical positivism and ordinary language philosophy have similarities with pragmatism. Like pragmatism, logical positivism provides a verification criterion of meaning that is supposed to rid us of nonsense metaphysics. However, logical positivism doesn't stress action like pragmatism does. Furthermore, the pragmatists rarely used their maxim of meaning to rule out all metaphysics as nonsense. Usually, pragmatism was put forth to correct metaphysical doctrines or to construct empirically verifiable ones rather than to provide a wholesale rejection.
Ordinary language philosophy is closer to pragmatism than other
philosophy
of language because of its nominalist character and
because it takes the broader functioning of language in an
environment as its focus instead of investigating abstract
relations between language and world.
Pragmatism has ties to
process
philosophy. Much of their work developed in dialogue with
process philosophers like Henri
Bergson and Alfred
North Whitehead, who aren't usually considered pragmatists
because they differ so much on other points. (Douglas Browning et
al. 1998; Rescher, SEP)
Behaviorism and
functionalism in
psychology and sociology also have ties to pragmatism, which is not
surprising considering that James and Dewey were both scholars of
psychology and that Mead
became a sociologist.
Utilitarianism
has some significant parallels to Pragmatism and John
Stuart Mill espoused similar values.
Criticism
Although many later pragmatists such as W.V.O. Quine were actually analytic philosophers, the most vehement criticisms of classical pragmatism came from within the analytic school. Bertrand Russell was especially known for his vituperative attacks on what he considered little more than epistemological relativism and short-sighted practicalism. Realists in general often could not fathom how pragmatists could seriously call themselves empirical or realist thinkers and thought pragmatist epistemology was only a disguised manifestation of idealism. (Hildebrand 2003)Louis Menand argues that
during the Cold War, the
intellectual life of the United States became dominated by
ideologies. Since pragmatism seeks "to avoid the violence inherent
in abstraction," it was not very popular at the time.
Neopragmatism
as represented by Richard Rorty has been criticized as relativistic
both by neoclassical pragmatists such as Susan Haack
(Haack 1997) and by many analytic philosophers (Dennett 1998).
Rorty's early analytical work, however, differs notably from his
later work which some, including Rorty himself, consider to be
closer to literary
criticism than to philosophy - most criticism is aimed at this
latter phase of Rorty's thought.
A list of pragmatists
Classical pragmatists (1850-1950)
- Charles Sanders Peirce (1839-1914): was the founder of American pragmatism (later called by Peirce pragmaticism). He wrote on a wide range of topics, from mathematical logic and semiotics to psychology.
- William James (1842-1910): influential psychologist and theorist of religion, as well as philosopher. First to be widely associated with the term "pragmatism" due to Peirce's lifelong unpopularity.
- John Dewey (1859-1952): prominent philosopher of education, referred to his brand of pragmatism as instrumentalism.
- F.C.S. Schiller (1864-1937): one of the most important pragmatists of his time, Schiller is largely forgotten today.
Important protopragmatists or
related thinkers
- George Herbert Mead (1863-1931): philosopher and social psychologist.
- Ralph Waldo Emerson (1803-1882): the American protopragmatist.
- Josiah Royce (1855-1916): colleague of James who employed pragmatism in an idealist metaphysical framework, he was particularly interested in the philosophy of religion and community; his work is often associated with neo-Hegelianism.
- George Santayana (1863-1952): often not considered to be a canonical pragmatist, he applied pragmatist methodologies to naturalism (philosophy), exemplified in his early masterwork, The Life of Reason.
Fringe figures
- Giovanni Papini (1881-1956): Italian essayist, mostly known because James occasionally mentioned him.
- Giovanni Vailati (1863-1909): Italian analytic and pragmatist philosopher.
Neoclassical pragmatists (1950-)
Neoclassical pragmatists stay closer to the project of the classical pragmatists than neopragmatists do.- Sidney Hook (1902-1989): a prominent New York intellectual and philosopher, a student of Dewey at Columbia.
- Isaac Levi (1930): seeks to apply pragmatist thinking in a decision-theoretic perspective.
- Susan Haack (1945): teaches at the University of Miami, sometimes called the intellectual granddaughter of C.S. Peirce, known chiefly for foundherentism.
- Larry Hickman: philosopher of technology and important Dewey scholar as head of the Center for Dewey Studies.
- David Hildebrand: like other scholars of the classical pragmatists, Hildebrandt is dissatisfied with neopragmatism and argues for the continued importance of the writings of John Dewey.
- Nicholas Rescher
Analytical, neo- and other pragmatists (1950-)
(Often labelled neopragmatism as well.)- Willard van Orman Quine (1908-2000): pragmatist philosopher, concerned with language, logic, and philosophy of mathematics.
- Clarence Irving Lewis (1883-1964).
- Richard Rorty (1931 - 2007): famous author of Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.
- Hilary Putnam: in many ways the opposite of Rorty and thinks classical pragmatism was too permissive a theory.
- Richard Shusterman: philosopher of art.
- Stephen Toulmin: student of Wittgenstein, known especially for his The Uses of Argument.
- John Hawthorne: Defends a pragmatist form of contextualism to deal with the lottery paradox in his Knowledge and Lotteries.
- Jason Stanley: Defends a pragmatist form of contextualism against semantic varieties of contextualism in his Knowledge and Practical Interest.
- Arthur Fine: Philosopher of Science who proposed the Natural Ontological Attitude to the debate of scientific realism.
- Joseph Margolis still proudly defends the original Pragmatists and sees his recent work on Cultural Realism as extending and deepening their insights, especially the contribution of Pierce and Dewey, in the context of a rapprochement with Continental philosophy.
- Robert Pirsig author of the philosophical novel, "Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance", rejects the primacy of the subject-object dichotomy and gives precedence to a concept he calls "dynamic quality" – the precognitive leading edge of reality. Pirsig considers dynamic quality to be the simple, direct stimulus to awareness. Pirsig acknowledges the similarity of his approach to that of other pragmatists, particularly James.
Other pragmatists
Legal pragmatists- Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.: justice of the Supreme Court of the United States.
- Stephen Breyer: U.S. Supreme Court Associate Justice.
- Richard Posner: Judge on U.S. Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit.
- Cornel West: thinker on race, politics, and religion; operates under the sign of "prophetic pragmatism".
- Wilfrid Sellars: broad thinker, attacked foundationalism in the analytic tradition.
- Frank P. Ramsey
- Karl-Otto Apel
- Randolph Bourne
Bibliography
- Elizabeth Anderson. Dewey's Moral Philosophy. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Douglas Browning, William T. Myers (Eds.) Philosophers of Process. 1998.
- Robert Burch. Charles Sanders Peirce. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- John Dewey. Donald F. Koch (ed.) Lectures on Ethics 1900–1901. 1991.
- Daniel Dennett. Postmodernism and Truth. 1998.
- John Dewey. The Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action. 1929.
- John Dewey. Three Independent Factors in Morals. 1930.
- John Dewey. The Influence of Darwin on Philosophy and Other Essays. 1910.
- John Dewey. Experience & Education. 1938.
- Cornelis De Waal. On Pragmatism. 2005.
- Abraham Edel. Pragmatic Tests and Ethical Insights. In: Ethics at the Crossroads: Normative Ethics and Objective Reason. George F. McLean, Richard Wollak (eds.) 1993.
- Michael Eldridge. Transforming Experience: John Dewey's Cultural Instrumentalism. 1998.
- Richard Field. John Dewey (1859-1952). Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- David L. Hildebrand. Beyond Realism & Anti-Realism. 2003.
- David L. Hildebrand. The Neopragmatist Turn. Southwest Philosophy Review Vol. 19, no. 1. January, 2003.
- William James. Pragmatism, A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, Popular Lectures on Philosophy. 1907.
- William James The Will to Believe. 1896.
- George Lakoff and Mark Johnson. Philosophy in the Flesh : The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought. 1929.
- Todd Lekan. Making Morality: Pragmatist Reconstruction in Ethical Theory. 2003.
- C.I. Lewis. Mind and the World Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge. 1929.
- Keya Maitra. On Putnam. 2003.
- Joseph Margolis. Historied Thought, Constructed World. 1995.
- Louis Menand. The Metaphysical Club. 2001.
- Hilary Putnam Reason, Truth and History. 1981.
- W.V.O. Quine. Two Dogmas of Empiricism. Philosophical Review. January 1951.
- W.V.O. Quine Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. 1969.
- N. Rescher. Process Philosophy. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Richard Rorty Rorty Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers. Volume 3. 1998.
- Stephen Toulmin. The Uses of Argument. 1958.
Notes and other sources
Papers and online encyclopedias are part of the bibliography. Other sources may include interviews, reviews and websites.- Gary A. Olson and Stephen Toulmin. Literary Theory, Philosophy of Science, and Persuasive Discourse: Thoughts from a Neo-premodernist. Interview in JAC 13.2. 1993.
- Susan Haack. Vulgar Rortyism. Review in The New Criterion. November 1997.
- Pietarinen, A.V. “Interdisciplinarity and Peirce's classification of the Sciences: A Centennial Reassessment," Perspectives on Science, 14(2), 127-152 (2006).
Resources
Important introductory primary texts Note that this is an introductory list: some important works are left out and some less monumental works that are excellent introductions are included.- C.S. Peirce, How to Make Our Ideas Clear (paper)
- C.S. Peirce, A Definition of Pragmatism (paper)
- William James, Pragmatism (especially lectures I, II and VI)
- John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy
- John Dewey, Three Independent factors in Morals (paper)
- John Dewey, A short catechism concerning truth (chapter)
- W.V.O. Quine, Three Dogmas of Empiricism (paper)
Secondary texts
- Cornelis De Waal, On Pragmatism
- Louis Menand, The Metaphysical Club
- Hilary Putnam, Pragmatism: An Open Question
- Abraham Edel, Pragmatic Tests and Ethical Insights
- D. S. Clarke, Rational Acceptance and Purpose
- Haack, Susan & Lane, Robert, Eds. (2006). Pragmatism Old and New: Selected Writings. New York: Prometheus Books.
- Louis Menand, ed., Pragmatism: A Reader (includes essays by Peirce, James, Dewey, Rorty, others)
Journals There are several
peer-reviewed journals dedicated to pragmatism, for example
Online resources
practical in Arabic:
براغماتية
practical in Bulgarian:
Прагматизъм
practical in Czech:
Pragmatismus
practical in German:
Pragmatismus
practical in Spanish:
Pragmatismo
practical in French:
Pragmatisme
practical in Ido:
Pragmatismo
practical in Icelandic:
Gagnhyggja
practical in Italian:
Pragmatismo
practical in Hebrew:
פרגמטיזם
practical in Lithuanian:
Pragmatizmas
practical in Hungarian:
Pragmatizmus
practical in Dutch:
Pragmatisme
practical in Japanese:
プラグマティズム
practical in Norwegian:
Pragmatisme
practical in Pushto:
پراګماتيزم
practical in Polish:
Pragmatyzm
practical in Portuguese:
Pragmatismo
practical in Russian:
Прагматизм
practical in Sardinian:
Pragmatismu
practical in Slovak:
Pragmatizmus
practical in Serbian:
Прагматизам
practical in Finnish:
Pragmatismi
practical in Swedish:
Pragmatism
practical in Tamil:
காரியவாதம்
practical in Vietnamese: chủ
nghĩa thực dụng
practical in Ukrainian:
Прагматизм
practical in Urdu:
استناجیت
practical in Chinese:
实用主义
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
achievable, actable, adaptable, advantageous, appliable, applicable, applied, appropriate, attainable, balanced, banausic, beneficial, breadwinning, businesslike, commercial, commodious, commonsense, compassable, compliant, constructive, convenient, cool, coolheaded, doable, down-to-earth, ductile, earthy, effective, effectual, efficacious, efficient, empirical, employable, everyday, expedient, exploitable, feasible, field, fitting, flexible, foolproof, functional, go, good for, handy, hard, hard-boiled, hard-nosed,
hardheaded, helpful, hoaxproof, judicious, levelheaded, logical, malleable, manageable, maneuverable, manipulable, manipulatable, materialistic,
matter-of-fact, moneymaking, mundane, negotiable, not born
yesterday, of general utility, of help, of service, of use,
old, old-time, operable, operatable, operational, operative, ordinary, overcomable, performable, personal, philosophical, pliable, pliant, positivistic, practicable,
practical-minded, practiced, pragmatic, pragmatical, proper, prosaic, rational, realist, realistic, realizable, reasonable, reusable, sane, scientific, scientistic, seasoned, secular, sensible, serviceable, skilled, sober, sober-minded, sophisticated, sound, sound-thinking,
straight-thinking, superable, surmountable, tough-minded,
tractable, uncullible, undeceivable, undeludable, undupable, unfoolable, ungullible, unhoaxable, unideal, unidealistic, unromantic, unseduceable, unsentimental, untroublesome, usable, useable, useful, utilitarian, utilizable, versed, vet, veteran, viable, virtual, well-balanced, wieldable, wieldy, wise, workable, workaday, workday, working, worldly, yielding